Definition 9.2.8.1. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an $\infty $-category. We say that $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is essentially finite if there exists a categorical equivalence $K \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $K$ is a finite simplicial set.
9.2.8 Finiteness Conditions on $\infty $-Categories
The results of ยง9.2.7 have counterparts for the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ of small $\infty $-categories.
Let $X$ be a Kan complex. We have now given two definitions of what it means for $X$ to be essentially finite:
According to Definition 9.2.7.1, $X$ is essentially finite if there exists a finite simplicial set $K$ and a weak homotopy equivalence $K \rightarrow X$.
According to Definition 9.2.8.1, $X$ is essentially finite if there exists a finite simplicial set $K$ and a categorical equivalence $K \rightarrow X$.
However, there is no conflict: we will see in a moment that these conditions are equivalent (Proposition 9.2.8.4).
Lemma 9.2.8.2. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an $\infty $-category which is essentially finite. Suppose we are given a diagram $f_0: K_0 \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $K_0$ is a finite simplicial set. Then $f_0$ factors as a composition $K_0 \xrightarrow {u} K \xrightarrow {f} \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $u$ is a monomorphism, $K$ is a finite simplicial set, and $f$ is a categorical equivalence of simplicial sets.
Proof. Since $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is essentially finite, we can choose a categorical equivalence $U_0: \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_0 \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_0$ is a finite simplicial set. Arguing as in the proof of Proposition 4.1.3.2, we can factor $U_0$ as a composition $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_0 \xrightarrow {j} \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}\xrightarrow {U} \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $U$ is an inner fibration and $j$ is a transfinite composition of pushouts of inner horn inclusions. More precisely, we may assume that $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}= \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_{\beta }$ for some ordinal $\beta $ and some well-ordered diagram
having the following properties:
For every ordinal $\alpha < \beta $, there is a pair of integers $0 < i < n$ and a pushout diagram of simplicial sets
\[ \xymatrix@R =50pt@C=50pt{ \Lambda ^{n}_{i} \ar [r] \ar [d] & \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_{\alpha } \ar [d] \\ \Delta ^{n} \ar [r]^{ \sigma _{\alpha } } & \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_{\alpha +1}. } \]In what follows, we will identify $\sigma _{\alpha }$ with an $n$-simplex of $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$ and write $\tau _{\alpha }$ for its $i$th face $d^{n}_{i}( \sigma _{\alpha } )$.
For every nonzero limit ordinal $\lambda \leq \beta $, the comparison map $\varinjlim _{\alpha < \lambda } \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_{\alpha } \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_{\lambda }$ is an isomorphism.
Let us say that a simplicial subset $S \subseteq \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$ is saturated if, whenever $S$ contains the simplex $\tau _{\alpha }$, then it also contains the simplex $\sigma _{\alpha }$. If $S$ is any simplicial subset of $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$, then there is a smallest saturated simplicial subset $S^{+}$ which contains $S$. Moreover, if $S$ is finite, then $S^{+}$ is also finite.
Since $U$ is an inner fibration, $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$ is an $\infty $-category. Since $U_0$ and $j$ are categorical equivalences of simplicial sets, the functor $U$ is an equivalence of $\infty $-categories, and therefore admits a homotopy inverse $U^{-1}: \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}\rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$. Let $L \subseteq \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$ be the smallest saturated simplicial subset which contains both $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_0$ and the image of the diagram $(U^{-1} \circ f_0): K_0 \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$. For $\alpha \leq \beta $, set $L_{\alpha } = L \cap \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_{\alpha }$. Then the inclusion map $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_0 = L_0 \hookrightarrow L_{\beta } = L$ can be realized as a transfinite composition of morphisms $L_{\alpha } \hookrightarrow L_{\alpha +1}$, each of which is either a pushout of an inner horn inclusion (if the simplex $\sigma _{\alpha }$ is contained in $L$) or an isomorphism (if $\sigma _{\alpha }$ is not contained in $L$). In particular, the inclusion $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}_0 \hookrightarrow L$ is inner anodyne, so that $U|_{L}: L \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is a categorical equivalence of simplicial sets.
By construction, the composition $U^{-1} \circ f_0$ can be regarded as a morphism of simplicial sets $g: K_0 \rightarrow L$. Set $f_{1} = U|_{L} \circ g$. Since $U^{-1}$ is a homotopy inverse to $U$, $f_0$ and $f_{1}$ are isomoprhic when regarded as objects of the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{Fun}(K, \operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$. Let $Q$ be a finite simplicial set equipped with a monomorphism $e: \Delta ^1 \hookrightarrow Q$ which exhibits $Q$ as a localization of $\Delta ^1$ with respect to its nondegenerate edge (for example, we can take $Q$ to be the quotient of $\Delta ^3$ appearing in Corollary 6.3.2.8). Let $q_0$ and $q_1$ be the vertices of $Q$ given by the source and target of the edge $e$. Our assumption that $f_0$ and $f_1$ are isomorphic is then equivalent to the assertion that there exists a diagram $h: Q \rightarrow \operatorname{Fun}(K_0, \operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$ satisfying $h(q_0) = f_0$ and $h(q_1) = f_1$. Let us identify $h$ with a morphism of simplicial sets $H: Q \times K_0 \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$.
Note that the projection map $Q \rightarrow \Delta ^0$ is a categorical equivalence of simplicial sets (see Corollary 6.3.2.7), so the inclusion $\{ q_1 \} \hookrightarrow Q$ has the same property. Form a pushout diagram
so that the left vertical map determines a categorical equivalence $L \hookrightarrow K$ (Remark 4.5.4.13). By construction, there is a unique morphism of simplicial sets $f: K \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ satisfying $f|_{L} = U|_{L}$ and $f|_{ (Q \times K_0) } = H$. Since $U|_{L}$ is a categorical equivalence, it follows that $f$ is a categorical equivalence. We conclude by observing that $f_0$ can be recovered as the composition $f \circ u$, where $u$ is the monomorphism given by the composition
Proposition 9.2.8.3. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an essentially finite $\infty $-category and let $W$ be a finite collection of morphisms of $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$. Then the localization $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}[W^{-1}]$ is also essentially finite.
Proof. Choose a categorical equivalence $F: \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_0 \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_0$ is a finite simplicial set. By virtue of Lemma 9.2.8.2, we can assume that $W = F(W_0)$, where $W_0$ is a collection of morphisms of $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_0$. In this case, we can identify $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}[W^{-1}]$ with a localization of $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_0$ with respect to $W_0$, which is essentially finite by virtue of Remark 6.3.2.10. $\square$
Definitions 9.2.8.1 and 9.2.7.1 are compatible with one another:
Proposition 9.2.8.4. Let $X$ be a Kan complex. The following conditions are equivalent:
The Kan complex $X$ is essentially finite in the sense of Definition 9.2.7.1: that is, there exists a finite simplicial set $K$ and a weak homotopy equivalence $f: K \rightarrow X$.
The Kan complex $X$ is essentially finite when viewed as an $\infty $-category, in the sense of Definition 9.2.8.1: that is, there exists a finite simplicial set $K$ and a categorical equivalence $K \rightarrow X$.
Proof. The implication $(2) \Rightarrow (1)$ is trivial, since every categorical equivalence of simplicial sets is a weak homotopy equivalence (Remark 4.5.3.4). We now prove the converse. Assume that there exists a weak homotopy equivalence $f: K \rightarrow X$, where $K$ is a finite simplicial set. Then $f$ factors as a composition $K \xrightarrow {i} \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}\xrightarrow {F} X$, where $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is an $\infty $-category and $i$ is a categorical equivalence of simplicial sets (Proposition 4.1.3.2). Let $W$ be the collection of all edges of $K$. Since $f$ is a weak homotopy equivalence, it exhibits the Kan complex $X$ as a localization of $K$ with respect to $W$ (Proposition 6.3.1.21). It follows that the functor $F$ exhibits $X$ as a localization of $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ with respect to $i(W)$. Since $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is an essentially finite $\infty $-category, Proposition 9.2.8.3 implies that $X$ is also an essentially finite $\infty $-category. $\square$
Remark 9.2.8.5. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an $\infty $-category. Choose a weak homotopy equivalence $F: \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}\rightarrow X$, where $X$ is a Kan complex (for example, we could take $X = \operatorname{Ex}^{\infty }(\operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$). Suppose that $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is essentially finite: that is, that there exists a categorical equivalence of simplicial sets $G: K \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$. Then the composite map $(G \circ F): K \rightarrow X$ is a weak homotopy equivalence, so that $X$ is an essentially finite when regarded as a Kan complex. It follows from Proposition 9.2.8.4 that $X$ is also essentially finite when regarded as an $\infty $-category.
Proposition 9.2.8.6. Suppose we are given a categorical pushout diagram of $\infty $-categories If $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_0$, and $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_1$ are essentially finite, then $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{01}$ is essentially finite.
Proof. Using Lemma 9.2.8.2, we can construct a commutative diagram of simplicial sets
where the vertical maps are categorical equivalences, the upper horizontal maps are monomorphisms, and the simplicial sets $K_0$, $K$, and $K_1$ are finite. Our assumption that (9.5) is a categorical pushout square then guarantees that the induced map $K_0 \amalg _{K} K_1 \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{01}$ is a categorical equivalence (Proposition 4.5.4.9), so that the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{01}$ is also essentially finite. $\square$
Corollary 9.2.8.7. The collection of essentially finite $\infty $-categories is closed under the formation of finite colimits (formed in the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$).
Proof. Since the initial object $\emptyset \in \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ is essentially finite, it will suffice to show that essential finiteness is closed under the formation of pushouts (see Corollary 7.6.2.30). This is a reformulation of Proposition 9.2.8.6 (see Example 7.6.3.4). $\square$
Proposition 9.2.8.8. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ denote the smallest full subcategory of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ which is closed under finite colimits and contains $\Delta ^1$. Then an $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ if and only if it is essentially finite.
Proof. For every simplicial set $K$, we can choose a categorical equivalence $K \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is an $\infty $-category. Let us say that $K$ is good if the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ (note that this condition is invariant under equivalence, and therefore depends only on $K$). We will show that every finite simplicial set $K$ is good: that is, every essentially finite $\infty $-category belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$; the converse is an immediate consequence of Corollary 9.2.8.7. Our proof proceeds in several steps:
- $(a)$
The simplicial set $\Delta ^1$ is good (since it is an $\infty $-category which belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$).
- $(b)$
Let $f: K \rightarrow K'$ be a categorical equivalence of simplicial sets. Then $K$ is good if and only if $K'$ is good.
- $(c)$
The collection of good simplicial sets is closed under finite coproducts (since $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ is closed under finite coproducts in $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$; see Corollary 4.5.3.10 and Example 7.6.1.17).
- $(d)$
Suppose we are given a categorical pushout square of simplicial sets
\[ \xymatrix@R =50pt@C=50pt{ K_{01} \ar [r] \ar [d] & K_0 \ar [d] \\ K_1 \ar [r] & K. } \]If $K_0$, $K_1$, and $K_{01}$ are good, then $K$ is good. See Example 7.6.3.5.
- $(e)$
Let $K$ and $K'$ be simplicial sets containing vertices $x$ and $x'$, respectively, and let $K \vee K'$ denote the pushout $K \coprod _{ \Delta ^0 } K'$. If $K$ and $K'$ are good, then $K \vee K'$ is also good. To prove this, consider the diagram
\[ \xymatrix@R =50pt@C=50pt{ \Delta ^1 \amalg \Delta ^1 \ar [r] \ar [d] & \{ x\} \amalg \{ x'\} \ar [r] \ar [d] & K \amalg K' \ar [d] \\ \Delta ^1 \ar [r] & \Delta ^0 \ar [r] & K \vee K'. } \]The right half of the diagram is a pushout square in which the horizontal maps are monomorphisms, and therefore a categorical pushout square (Example 4.5.4.12). The left half of the diagram is a categorical pushout square by virtue of Proposition 6.3.2.4. Applying Proposition 4.5.4.8, we conclude that the outer rectangle is also a categorical pushout square. By virtue of $(d)$, it will suffice to show that the simplicial sets $\Delta ^1$, $\Delta ^1 \amalg \Delta ^1$, and $K \amalg K'$ are good. This follows from $(a)$ and $(b)$.
- $(f)$
Let $n$ be a positive integer, and let $\operatorname{Spine}[n]$ denote the spine of the standard $n$-simplex $\Delta ^ n$ (Example 1.5.7.7). Then the simplicial set $\operatorname{Spine}[n]$ is good. For $n = 1$, this follows from $(a)$. The general case follows by induction on $n$, using $(e)$.
- $(g)$
The standard $0$-simplex $\Delta ^0$ is good. To prove this, consider the diagram of simplicial sets
\[ \xymatrix@R =50pt@C=50pt{ \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }( \{ 0 < 1 \} ) \ar [r] \ar [d] & \operatorname{Spine}[2] \ar [d] \ar [r] & \operatorname{Spine}[2] / \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }( \{ 1 < 2 \} ) \ar [d] \\ \Delta ^0 \ar [r] & \operatorname{Spine}[2] / \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }( \{ 0 < 1 \} ) \ar [r] & \Delta ^0. } \]The left side and outer rectangle are pushout square in which the horizontal maps are monomorphisms, and therefore categorical pushout squares (Example 4.5.4.12). Applying Proposition 4.5.4.8, we see that the right side is also a categorical pushout square. Using $(d)$, we are reduced to proving that the simplicial set $\operatorname{Spine}[2]$ and its quotients $\operatorname{Spine}[2] / \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }( \{ 0 < 1 \} )$ and $\operatorname{Spine}[2] / \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }( \{ 1 < 2 \} )$ are good, which follows from $(f)$.
- $(h)$
For every integer $n$, the standard $n$-simplex $\Delta ^ n$ is good. For $n=0$, this follows from $(g)$. For $n > 0$, it follows from $(b)$ and $(f)$, since the inclusion map $\operatorname{Spine}[n] \hookrightarrow \Delta ^ n$ is a categorical equivalence (Example 1.5.7.7).
We now show that every finite simplicial set $K$ is good. If $K$ is empty, this follows from $(c)$. We may therefore assume that $K$ has dimension $d \geq 0$. Proceeding by induction on $d$ and on the number of nondegenerate simplices of $K$, we may assume that there exists a pushout square
where the simplicial sets $\operatorname{\partial \Delta }^ d$ and $K_0$ are good by our inductive hypothesis, and $\Delta ^ d$ is good by virtue of $(h)$. Since (9.6) is a categorical pushout square (Example 4.5.4.12), it follows from $(d)$ that that $K$ is also good. $\square$
Proposition 9.2.8.9. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an essentially finite $\infty $-category. Then $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is compact when regarded as an object of the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$.
Proof. Let $h^{\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}}: \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}\rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{S}}$ be the functor corepresented by $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$; we wish to show that the functor $h^{\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}}$ is finitary. By virtue of Corollary 9.1.9.13, it will suffice to show that the functor $h^{\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}}$ preserves the colimit of every diagram $\mathscr {F}: \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }(A) \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ indexed by a small directed partially ordered set $(A,\leq )$. Using Corollary 5.6.5.18, we can reduce to the case where $\mathscr {F}$ factors through the simplicial subset $\operatorname{N}_{\bullet }(\operatorname{QCat}) \subset \operatorname{N}_{\bullet }^{\operatorname{hc}}(\operatorname{QCat}) = \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$: that is, it is given by a diagram in the ordinary category of simplicial sets.
Choose a categorical equivalence $f: K \rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$, where $K$ is a finite simplicial set. Using Proposition 5.6.6.17, we can assume that $h^{\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}}$ is obtained as the homotopy coherent nerve of the simplicially enriched functor $\operatorname{Fun}(K, \bullet )^{\simeq }: \operatorname{QCat}\rightarrow \operatorname{Kan}$. In particular, we have a commutative diagram of $\infty $-categories
Consequently, to show that the functor $h^{\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}}$ preserves the colimit of the diagram $\mathscr {F}$, it will suffice to show that the vertical maps and upper horizontal map in this diagram preserve $\operatorname{N}_{\bullet }(A)$-indexed colimits. For the vertical maps, this follows from Corollary 9.1.6.3 and Variant 9.1.6.4. For the upper horizontal map, it follows from Variant 9.2.0.5. $\square$
Corollary 9.2.8.10. The inclusion functor $\iota : \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}} \hookrightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ exhibits $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ as an $\operatorname{Ind}$-completion of the full subcategory $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ of essentially finite $\infty $-categories.
Proof. The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ admits small filtered colimits (Corollary 7.4.5.3), and every object of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ is compact when viewed as an object of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ (Proposition 9.2.8.9). By virtue of Corollary 9.2.3.6, it will suffice to show that every small $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ can be realized as the colimit of a small filtered diagram $\{ \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha } \} $ in the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$, where each $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha }$ is essentially finite. Let $Q: \operatorname{Set_{\Delta }}\rightarrow \operatorname{Set_{\Delta }}$ be a finitary functor which associates to each simplicial set $K$ an $\infty $-category $Q(K)$ equipped with a categorical equivalence $u_ K: K \rightarrow Q(K)$ (Proposition 4.1.3.2). Without loss of generality, we may assume that $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}= Q(K)$ for some small simplicial set $K$. In this case, we can take $\{ \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha } \} $ to be the diagram $\{ Q( K_{\alpha } ) \} $, where $K_{\alpha }$ ranges over the collection fo all finite simplicial subsets of $K$ (see Remark 3.6.1.8). $\square$
Beware that the converse of Proposition 9.2.8.9 is false. This motivates the following:
Definition 9.2.8.11. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an $\infty $-category. We say that $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is finitely dominated if it is a retract (in the homotopy category $\mathrm{h} \mathit{\operatorname{QCat}}$) of an essentially finite $\infty $-category.
Remark 9.2.8.12. Let $X$ be a Kan complex. The following conditions are equivalent:
The Kan complex $X$ is finitely dominated in the sense of Definition 9.2.7.7: that is, it is a retract of an essentially finite Kan complex $Y$ (in the homotopy category $\mathrm{h} \mathit{\operatorname{Kan}}$).
The Kan complex $X$ is finitely dominated when regarded as an $\infty $-category, in the sense of Definition 9.2.8.11: that is, it is a retract of an essentially finite $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ (in the homotopy category $\mathrm{h} \mathit{\operatorname{QCat}}$).
The implication $(1) \Rightarrow (2)$ is immediate. For the converse, assume that $X$ is a retract of an essentially finite $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$. Then $X$ is also a retract of the Kan complex $\operatorname{Ex}^{\infty }(\operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$, which is also essentially finite (Remark 9.2.8.5).
Proposition 9.2.8.13. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be a small $\infty $-category. Then $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is finitely dominated if and only if it is compact when viewed as an object of the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$.
Proof. Combine Corollary 9.2.8.10 with Proposition 9.2.6.13. $\square$
Remark 9.2.8.14. It follows from Corollary 9.2.8.10 that the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ is compactly generated. In particular, it can be regarded as an $\operatorname{Ind}$-completion of the full subcategory $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \aleph _0}$ of finitely dominated $\infty $-categories (see Corollary 9.2.6.10), which is an idempotent completion of the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ (Proposition 9.2.6.13).
The infinitary counterpart of Proposition 9.2.8.13 is more straightforward.
Proposition 9.2.8.15. Let $\kappa $ be an uncountable regular cardinal and let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be an $\infty $-category. The following conditions are equivalent:
The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is essentially $\kappa $-small (Definition 4.7.5.1).
The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ belongs to the smallest full subcategory of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ which contains $\Delta ^1$ and is closed under $\kappa $-small colimits.
The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is $\kappa $-compact when viewed as an object of the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$.
In the formulation of Proposition 9.2.8.15, we have implicitly assumed that the cardinal $\kappa $ and the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ Following the convention of Remark 4.7.0.5, we can regard Proposition 9.2.8.15 as a special case of the following more precise assertion:
Proposition 9.2.8.16. Let $\kappa \trianglelefteq \lambda $ be uncountable regular cardinals and let $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ be a $\lambda $-small $\infty $-category. The following conditions are equivalent:
The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is essentially $\kappa $-small.
The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ belongs to the smallest full subcategory of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ which contains $\Delta ^1$ and is closed under $\kappa $-small colimits.
The $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is $(\kappa , \lambda )$-compact when viewed as an object of the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$.
Proof. Let $\operatorname{\mathcal{E}}\subseteq \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ be the smallest full subcategory which contains $\Delta ^1$ and is closed under $\kappa $-filtered colimits. Applying Proposition 9.2.8.8, we conclude that every essentially finite $\infty $-category belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{E}}$. Let $Q: \operatorname{Set_{\Delta }}\rightarrow \operatorname{Set_{\Delta }}$ be as in the proof of Proposition 9.2.8.13. If $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is a $\kappa $-small simplicial set, then it can be realized as the colimit of a $\kappa $-small filtered diagram $\{ \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha } \} $ of finite simplicial sets $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha }$, so that $Q( \operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$ is the colimit of a $\kappa $-small filtered diagram $\{ Q(\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha } ) \} $ in the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$. Since each $Q(\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha } )$ is essentially finite, it follows that $Q( \operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$ belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{E}}$. If $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is an $\infty $-category, then it is equivalent to $Q(\operatorname{\mathcal{C}})$ and therefore also belongs to $\operatorname{\mathcal{E}}$. This establishes the implication $(1) \Rightarrow (2)$.
The implication $(2) \Rightarrow (3)$ follows from Proposition 9.2.2.21. We will complete the proof by showing that $(3)$ implies $(1)$. Combining Variant 9.1.7.21 with Corollary 9.1.6.3, we see that $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ is generated by $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \kappa }$ under $\lambda $-small, $\kappa $-filtered colimits. Applying Lemma 9.2.6.12, we conclude that if $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ is $(\kappa ,\lambda )$-compact, then it is a retract of a $\kappa $-small $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$. In particular, it can be realized as the colimit of a diagram
in the $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{<\lambda }$, for some (homotopy idempotent) functor $F: \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}\rightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{D}}$. Forming the colimit of this diagram in the ordinary category of simplicial sets, we obtain a $\kappa $-small $\infty $-category which is equivalent to $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ (see Example 7.6.5.8). $\square$
Corollary 9.2.8.17. Let $\kappa $ and $\lambda $ be uncountable regular cardinals satisfying $\kappa \trianglelefteq \lambda $. Then the inclusion map $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \kappa } \hookrightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ exhibits $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ as an $\operatorname{Ind}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }$-completion of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \kappa }$.
Proof. Note that $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ admits $\lambda $-small colimits (Corollary 7.4.5.22), and that objects of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \kappa }$ are $(\kappa ,\lambda )$-compact when viewed as objects of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ (Proposition 9.2.8.16). By virtue of Proposition 9.2.3.3, it will suffice to show that every $\lambda $-small $\infty $-category $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}$ can be realized as the colimit of a $\lambda $-small, $\kappa $-filtered colimit $\{ \operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha } \} $, where each $\operatorname{\mathcal{C}}_{\alpha }$ is $\kappa $-small. This follows from Variant 9.1.7.21 and Corollary 9.1.6.3. $\square$
Remark 9.2.8.18. The conclusion of Corollary 9.2.8.17 is also correct in the case $\kappa = \aleph _0$, following the convention that $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \aleph _0}$ is the full subcategory of $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}$ spanned by its compact objects (see Definition 9.2.2.6). Alternatively, we can replace $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \aleph _0}$ with the subcategory $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{\mathrm{fin}}$ of essentially finite $\infty $-categories (compare with Corollary 9.2.8.10).
Remark 9.2.8.19. For every pair of uncountable regular cardinals $\kappa \leq \lambda $, the inclusion map $\operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \kappa } \hookrightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ induces a fully faithful functor $\operatorname{Ind}_{\kappa }^{\lambda }( \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \kappa } ) \hookrightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{QC}}_{< \lambda }$ (see Proposition 9.2.3.1).
Corollary 9.2.8.20. Let $\kappa $ be a small uncountable regular cardinal. Then the inclusion functor $\operatorname{\mathcal{S}}_{< \kappa } \hookrightarrow \operatorname{\mathcal{S}}$ exhibits $\operatorname{\mathcal{S}}$ as an $\operatorname{Ind}_{\kappa }$-completion of $\operatorname{\mathcal{S}}_{< \kappa }$.
Proof. Apply Corollary 9.2.8.17 in the special case where $\lambda = \operatorname{\textnormal{\cjRL {t}}}$ is a strongly inaccessible cardinal. $\square$